And the Spirit & the bride say, come.... Reveaaltion 22:17

And the Spirit & the bride say, come.... Reveaaltion 22:17
And the Spirit & the bride say, come...Revelation 22:17 - May We One Day Bow Down In The DUST At HIS FEET ...... {click on blog TITLE at top to refresh page}---QUESTION: ...when the Son of man cometh, shall he find faith on the earth? LUKE 18:8

Sunday, January 15, 2017

Creation Moment 1/16/2017 - Set Theory & the CREATOR

Below, the article demonstrates with SET THEORY from Mathematics, that the new argument floating around atheistic evolutionary circles these days---that something can come from nothing, the nothing being quantum fluctuations---shows that their argument is rooted in a Falsehood.
(Besides COMMON SENSE would dictate that energy, the quantum fluctuations, is something). So  the atheists keep backing themselves into a ditch.

 For it is written, He taketh the wise in their own craftiness.
1 Corinthians 3:19

"As Joan Bagaria stated, “The formal language of pure set theory allows [us] to formalize all mathematical notions and arguments. Thus, set theory has become the standard foundation for mathematics, as every mathematical object can be viewed as a set, and every theorem of mathematics can be logically deduced in the Predicate Calculus from the axioms of set theory”.

According to Liang Zongju, after Cauchy, “the most important advancement in the logical foundation of calculus was the construction of the real numbers using set theory.” Zongju argued that set theory helped with “the logical foundation of calculus” in that theories of calculus use the properties of real numbers derived from a “theory of real numbers”.

Robin W. Knight has recognized the notion that set theory is foundational for higher mathematics ontologically and epistemologically. The ontological foundation allows for the expression of complex structures and number sets, including real numbers. The epistemological foundation can be understood in light of the ability of mathematical questions to be reducible to questions concerning Set Theory.

This point about the set theory connection with algebra and calculus is important to make because modern physics stands upon the shoulders of algebra and calculus as it concerns the descriptions of reality. Consequently, one could argue that the definitions supplied by set theory may have relevance to modern science. This includes the definition of “nothing.”

The closest thing to “nothing” in set theory is the empty set. The tendency toward reductionism in set theory leads to there being only one empty set in reference to a given set, even if the given set is equal to an empty set. (This is comparable to someone recognizing that the value of zero can be added to any given algebraic term, including a term that equals zero. However, given the reductionism, we don’t go on with adding zeros to zeros ad infinitum.) The value of (absolute) zero is the value parallel to the empty set grouping.

Consequently, we end up with the rather informal philosophical statement that there can be nothing less than nothing. (This is comparable to saying that there is nothing less than absolute zero, as it concerns the quantity of anything. Absolute zero can also be viewed in terms of a calculus limit in a function. When graphed, one sees that a quantity of something already present may constantly approach absolute zero without ever reaching it.) If an entity can be conceived that is less than what we have called “nothing” and yet is not itself that “nothing,” then what we have called “nothing” cannot be “nothing” in a genuine sense. We can conceive of a “nothing” that is less than quantum fluctuations. Therefore, quantum fluctuations cannot be “nothing.” Actually, the absence of such fluctuations would get us closer to “nothing.”
In short, one could argue as follows:

Premise 1: Algebra and calculus depend on Set Theory for functional description.
Premise 2: This functional description includes absolute “nothing.”
Intermediate Conclusion 1 (IC1): Therefore, algebra and calculus depend on a Set Theory view of “nothing” (when dealing in absolute terms).
Premise 3: The philosophical definition of “nothing” is philosophically consistent with how Set Theory would view “nothing.”
Intermediate conclusion 2: Therefore, given P3 and IC1, the philosophical definition of “nothing” is philosophically consistent with how algebra and calculus would view absolute “nothing.”
Premise 4: Modern physics depends on algebra and calculus for descriptions of physical reality.
Premise 5: Included in the set of options for descriptions of physical reality is the description of “nothing.”
Consequential Conclusion: Therefore, given all of the above, modern physics depends on the philosophical definition of “nothing” for descriptions of “nothing” in physical reality.

In other words, through the intersection between philosophy and mathematics that is Set Theory, the same version of nothing that undergirds philosophy must also undergird the science of physics; otherwise, we are being inconsistent either in our science or our philosophy or both.
Conclusion
Ultimately, I propose that set theory can help us to understand more. The paradigm deals principally with identity and relationships of membership. Consequently, set theory can help us understand the
nature of basic configurations.

As the nature of apologetics arguments become more refined and scholarly, the apologetics community is going to have to discuss matters on the levels of paradigms such as set theory. Thinking in such paradigms may lead to refining of our wording of classical arguments as well. As more scholars enter the religion debates from various fields—history, classics, law, mathematics, and others—the apologetics community will need to have more specialists and more awareness of how mathematics can support (or not support) apologetics arguments." Z.E.Kendall